Научная статья на тему 'Причинность, моделирование и социальные нормы: их место в теоретическом ядре гетеродоксной экономики'

Причинность, моделирование и социальные нормы: их место в теоретическом ядре гетеродоксной экономики Текст научной статьи по специальности «Философия, этика, религиоведение»

CC BY
112
19
i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.
Ключевые слова
ГЕТЕРОДОКСНАЯ ЭКОНОМИКА / МЕТОДОЛОГИЯ ЭКОНОМИЧЕСКОЙ НАУКИ / МОДЕЛИРОВАНИЕ / ПРИЧИННОСТЬ / МЕТОДОЛОГИЧЕСКИЙ ИНДИВИДУАЛИЗМ / СОЦИАЛЬНЫЕ НОРМЫ / HETERODOX ECONOMICS / ECONOMIC METHODOLOGY / CAUSALITY / MODELLING / METHODOLOGICAL INDIVIDUALISM / SOCIAL NORMS

Аннотация научной статьи по философии, этике, религиоведению, автор научной работы — Синдзингре Алиса Николь

Дефиниции, используемые в рамках неортодоксальных экономических теорий и теоретические положения, составляющие их ядро, по-прежнему являются предметом дискуссий, равно как и определения и положения в рамках экономического мейнстрима. В связи с этим обсуждаются теоретические элементы, которые бы способствовали однозначному разграничению обеих позиций. В рамках неортодоксальных течений непросто выделить общие черты. Точно так же и мейнстрим нелегко описать посредством необходимых и достаточных характеристик, поскольку многочисленные авторы, по их собственным утверждениям, своим вкладом обогатили неоклассический экономикс, привнеся в него концепции из других социальных наук. С другой стороны, создаётся впечатление, что политику представителей неортодоксальных направлений и её отличия от мейнстрима (например, в оношении «строгости») легче идентифицировать. Несмотря на неопределенности данного характера, в настоящей статье показано, что некоторые ключевые концепции и теоретические допущения могут служить водоразделом между неортодоксальными течениями и экономичсеким иейнстримом. Значимость статьи заключается в обосновании того, что множество считающихся привычными различий между данными областями на самом деле не могут рассматриваться в качестве однозначных критериев для разграничения эпистемологических основ этих двух областей (например, эгоистичные агенты, методология моделирования, использование концепций социальных наук). Также в статье предложены несколько теоретических аспектов, которые могли бы служить ориентиром для такого разграничения в частности, связанные с принципом причинности, концепциями времени и общества.

i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.
iНе можете найти то, что вам нужно? Попробуйте сервис подбора литературы.
i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.

Causality, Modelling, Social Norms: Among the Theoretical Cores of ‘Heterodox’ Economics?

The definitions and theoretical cores of ‘heterodox’ economics remain subject to debate, as do those of ‘mainstream’ economics. The theoretical elements that could unambiguously differentiate both perspectives are therefore debated. Common features are difficult to highlight within ‘heterodox’ economics. Symmetrically, ‘mainstream’ economics is uneasy to describe via necessary and sufficient features, as numerous authors within its field claim to have enriched neoclassical economics, and to use concepts from other social sciences. On the other hand, ‘heterodox’ policies and their differences with mainstream ones (e.g., ‘austerity’) appear to be more identifiable. Despite these uncertainties, the paper shows that some core concepts and theoretical assumptions may represent a distinction between heterodox and mainstream economics. The contribution of the paper is to argue that many conventional distinctions may in fact not be unambiguous criteria of distinguishing the two epistemic frameworks (e.g., self-interested agents, the methodology of modelling, use of concepts of social sciences), and to suggest a few theoretical issues that could constitute lines of difference notably related to the concepts of causality, time and society.

Текст научной работы на тему «Причинность, моделирование и социальные нормы: их место в теоретическом ядре гетеродоксной экономики»

www.hjournal.ru DOI: 10.17835/2076-6297.2018.10.4.020-037

ПРИЧИННОСТЬ, МОДЕЛИРОВАНИЕ И СОЦИАЛЬНЫЕ НОРМЫ: ИХ МЕСТО В ТЕОРЕТИЧЕСКОМ ЯДРЕ ГЕТЕРОДОКСНОЙ ЭКОНОМИКИ

СИНДЗИНГРЕ АЛИСА НИКОЛЬ,

приглашенный профессор, Школа восточных и африканских исследований,

Университет Лондона, Центр экономики, Университет Париж-Север-13, email: ansindzingre@orange.fr

оо ■н о см

о ■н

Дефиниции, используемые в рамках неортодоксальных экономических теорий и теоретические положения, составляющие их ядро, по-прежнему являются предметом дискуссий, равно как и определения и положения в рамках экономического мейнстрима. В связи с этим обсуждаются теоретические элементы, которые бы способствовали однозначному разграничению обеих позиций. В рамках неортодоксальных течений непросто выделить общие черты. Точно так же и мейнстрим нелегко описать £ посредством необходимых и достаточных характеристик, поскольку многочисленные ф авторы, по их собственным утверждениям, своим вкладом обогатили неоклассический г£ экономикс, привнеся в него концепции из других социальных наук. С другой стороны, создаётся впечатление, что политику представителей неортодоксальных о направлений и её отличия от мейнстрима (например, в оношении «строгости») ^ легче идентифицировать. Несмотря на неопределенности данного характера, в о настоящей статье показано, что некоторые ключевые концепции и теоретические

2 допущения могут служить водоразделом между неортодоксальными течениями и 5 экономичсеким иейнстримом. Значимость статьи заключается в обосновании того, | что множество считающихся привычными различий между данными областями ° на самом деле не могут рассматриваться в качестве однозначных критериев ^ для разграничения эпистемологических основ этих двух областей (например, ? эгоистичные агенты, методология моделирования, использование концепций | социальных наук). Также в статье предложены несколько теоретических аспектов,

которые могли бы служить ориентиром для такого разграничения - в частности, связанные с принципом причинности, концепциями времени и общества.

Ключевые слова: гетеродоксная экономика; методология экономической науки; ш моделирование; причинность; методологический индивидуализм; социальные нормы. о

3

I—

ф

< о

<

CD X

Ф ¿L

LL

о <

ее -

о © Синдзингре А. Н., 2018

CAUSALITY, MODELLING, SOCIAL NORMS: AMONG THE THEORETICAL CORES OF 'HETERODOX' ECONOMICS?1

ALICE NICOLE SINDZINGRE,

Visiting lecturer, School of Oriental and African Studies (SOAS),

University of London, Centre d'Economie Paris-Nord (CEPN), University Paris-13 (France). email: ansindzingre@orange.fr

The definitions and theoretical cores of 'heterodox' economics remain subject to debate, as do those of 'mainstream'economics. The theoretical elements that could unambiguously differentiate both perspectives are therefore debated. Common features are difficult to highlight within 'heterodox'economics. Symmetrically, 'mainstream' economics is uneasy to describe via necessary and sufficient features, as numerous authors within its field claim to have enriched neoclassical economics, and to use concepts from other social sciences. On the other hand, heterodox'policies and their differences with mainstream ones (e.g., 'austerity') appear to be more identifiable. Despite these uncertainties, the paper shows that some core concepts and theoretical assumptions may represent a distinction between heterodox and mainstream economics. The contribution of the paper is to argue that many conventional distinctions may in fact not be unambiguous criteria of distinguishing the two epistemic frameworks (e.g., self-interested agents, the methodology of modelling, use of concepts of social sciences), and to suggest a few theoretical issues that could constitute lines of difference - notably related to the concepts of causality, time and society.

Keywords: heterodox economics; economic methodology; causality; modelling; methodological individualism; social norms

JEL: B00; B5

oo

■H

1. Introduction °

The definitions and theoretical cores of 'heterodox' economics remain subject to debate, ^t

as do those of 'mainstream' economics. The theoretical elements that could unambiguously °

differentiate both perspectives are therefore debated. 0-

The field of 'heterodox' economics is divided, thereby affecting the use of the concept,

as the latter includes approaches in which common features are difficult to highlight (post- ;>

Keynesian, 'old-institutional, Marxist, Austrian, etc). Centrifugal forces, and even deep #

disagreements (Dobusch and Kapeller, 2012), are such that, e.g., a Marxian economist can ¡^

view agent-based models, or economics of complexity, as fully 'mainstream' and hence open Q

to criticism. Similarly, Schumpeterian economics may be viewed as 'mainstream' by some ¡^

'heterodox' economists, but part of 'heterodoxy' by others; likewise, Austrian legacies can ^

be viewed as 'heterodox', as they diverge from the neoclassical framework, but as situated ^

outside heterodoxy in their defence of 'freedom', Hayekian 'spontaneous order', and in their t^

support for the restraining of state intervention2. As argued by Boyer (2017), economics, and ^ especially macroeconomics, has been characterised by the abandonment of general theory together with a rise in applied economics, and the various heterodoxies 'struggle separately to conquer hegemony' rather than seeking to define common bases.

CD

O

<

1 This paper was presented at the 30th Conference of the European Association for Evolutionary Political Economy (EAEPE), in the ^ Special Session 'History, definition and theoretical cores of heterodox economics', Nice, 6-8 September 2018.

2 See, for example, the views advocated by the Mises Institute. https://mises.org

O

The very word 'heterodoxy' as a unifying concept may likewise be debated, and its link with the discipline of economics is a question in itself. Other social sciences are less affected by such a disjunction within their domains: e.g., the expressions of 'heterodox linguistics', psychology, political science, etc, which could constitute sub-fields contrasting with 'orthodox linguistics', etc., are less recurrent in these disciplines — though occurrences exist (Phelps and White, 2018). Some non-mainstream economists indeed avoid the term 'heterodox' (as shown by, e.g., D'Ippoliti and Roncaglia, 2015; Mearman and Guizzo Archela, 2018). Moreover, for some observers sharp contrasts between mainstream and heterodox approaches may be 'counterproductive' and 'unconvincing' (Hodgson, 2005).

Symmetrically, 'mainstream' economics in the 21st century is uneasy to describe via necessary and sufficient features. Moreover, numerous authors within its field claim to have enriched the frameworks of marginalism or neoclassical economics, and to use concepts from other social sciences (e.g., among others, in institutional economics, positive political economics, or behavioural economics).

While the conceptual cores of 'heterodox' theories may not be easy to define, on the other hand, 'heterodox' policies and their differences with mainstream ones (e.g. 'austerity', privatisation, liberalisation vs. state intervention; supply-side vs. demand-side; 'capital' vs. 3 'labour', etc) appear to be more easily identifiable.

8 Despite these uncertainties, it is shown that some core concepts and theoretical

^ assumptions may represent a distinction between heterodox and mainstream economics. The contribution of the paper is thus: i) to argue that many conventional distinctions may in fact not be unambiguous criteria of distinguishing the two epistemic frameworks (e.g., mainstream economics would be characterised by a conception of individuals as driven by their interest, by methodological individualism, by modelling as an exclusive methodology, or by the dismissal of history or other social sciences); and ii) to suggest a few theoretical issues that appear under-investigated and constitute lines of differences between the two frameworks: i.e., respectively, the concepts of causality in the context of modelling, time and

o

■H

X CD m

< society - examined via the concept of social norms.

<

CD

X $

LU

The paper is structured as follows. Firstly, it presents a series of distinctions that the literature analyses as distinctions between the two frameworks, and shows that, in fact, they appear to be ambiguous and do not constitute necessary and sufficient criteria. Secondly, in

X X

< this context, the three issues of causality, time and conception of society are analysed as

X

O s

J >

relevant elements of distinction between the two frameworks.

2. The difficulty in drawing unambiguous distinctions 2.1. Defining 'mainstream' and 'heterodox' paradigms?

The literature is vast on the theoretical concepts that would characterise mainstream economic and heterodox perspectives, and this all the more since this is addressed within different disciplines, e.g., economic theory (macro and micro), epistemology, history of economic thought or methodology. This is why only a few points are discussed here, which can be viewed as important and under-investigated.

_i Mainstream economics?

z 'Mainstream economics' is notoriously difficult to define and the expression may be

P refused by the economists who otherwise are said to support its framework. It may refer to

tz marginalism, which has modelled economic outcomes in assuming the existence of a general

w equilibrium with an hypothetical auctioneer, the economic behaviour of individuals being

~ driven by prices as signals, and which has developed a concept of value grounded on that of

° utility. It has been noted that the main thinkers of marginalism (Leon Walras, William S.

^ Jevons, Carl Menger) did not use the expression 'neoclassical', which was in fact coined by

3 Thorstein Veblen in 1900 (Aspromourgos, 1986; De Vroey and Pensieroso, 2018). o

The concept of 'mainstream' economics remains debated and the strongest disagreements may occur within mainstream economics (Di Maio, 2013). For example, Walras' objective of establishing economics as a 'mathematical science' with mathematical models being 'truer than any other' was contested by a contemporary mathematical economists such as A. Cournot (Ragni, 2018). Equally, for some, the most important dissenters vis-à-vis mainstream economics do not come from heterodox economics, but from within the mainstream (Backhouse, 2010, who cites George Akerlof, Amartya Sen, Herbert Simon and Joseph Stiglitz as these key dissenters). Also, the fact that marginalism is a school of thought that succeeded classical political economy and preceded neoclassical economics remains debated (Lawson, 2013). Similarly the definition of classical political economy and the concepts it would have elaborated are a matter of debate (Martins, 2013): e.g., the analyses of a thinker such as Adam Smith have induced a great number of theoretical frameworks that can be viewed as contradictory (Weingast, 2018). Similarly, the deepening by Kenneth Arrow and Gerard Debreu of general equilibrium, according to some authors, can be viewed as dissenting or not, integrated or not, in the paradigm of general equilibrium (Duppe, 2012; Pignol, 2017; Berta, 2000).

'Mainstream economics' may also refer in the economics literature to the kind of economics that developed after WWII. Gathered under the expression of 'neoclassical economics', the latter typically assumes that economic agents maximise their utility and that this maximisation drives markets toward stable equilibria.

In the 21st century, however, such definitions of the 'mainstream' may have become less relevant in the context of the rise of applied economics (Backhouse and Cherrier, 2017), especially microeconomics at the expense of macroeconomics. This rise and associated preeminence of applied studies have been intensified by the availability of databases and 'big data' - features extraction from unstructured very large databases. Some mainstream studies may now claim that to be 'a-theoretical' constitutes 'real' and 'credible' science that avoids the 'ideological a-prioris' of theories (such as, among others, heterodox assumptions or qualitative analytic methods). In this perspective, the availability of a database is the start of an analysis, and good mainstream economics is the search for some correlation that statistical techniques can extract from that database, the latter being viewed as the essence of scientifically presented empirics. For example, the availability of satellite data on earth lights has generated a vast literature correlating them with growth, income, inequality, oo institutions, crop production, etc. (Donaldson and Storeygard, 2016), and collection of data o has become a highly regarded research activity - an example being the 2017 John Bates ^ Clark medal awarding the analysis of Indian railways by Donaldson (2018), who considers that economics is 'the physics of the social sciences, or physics for public policy' (Edwards, 2018).

o c

O ■H

Heterodox economics? q

'Heterodox' studies may thus be critical of certain positions of the abovementioned various & branches of economics, but not others, and therefore 'heterodox' stances may be as diverse as the branches of economics that constitute the 'mainstream'. Moreover, 'heterodox' critiques of mainstream economics may deploy at the macro level or at the micro level. Equally, these critiques can be theoretical or empirical; similarly, they may be 'internal' — refutation by inconsistencies — or 'external' critiques — refutation by other theories or facts (Hong, 2018).

The focus on methodological issues appears to constitute a commonality of the critiques ^ of the 'mainstream', with non-equilibrium, or historical modelling, being core elements: a w commonality to Marxian, neo-Austrian and post Keynesian economics — that would contrast ~ with mainstream economics — would thus be 'meta-methodological', with the latter being deductivist, reductionist and based on mathematical formalism, and the former relying on pluralistic reasoning and analysis of real problems (Dow, 2011; Lee, 2009). A common heterodox critique would thus be the opposition to the use of mathematical modelling, with its

expansion throughout the 20th century, as an exclusive tool of argumentation (De Vroey and Pensieroso, 2016). Hence heterodox studies would use concepts such as process rather than equilibrium, and, moreover, they would reject 'mathematical-deductivist methods' (Lawson, 2005). Heterodox studies here demonstrate that mainstream economics has substituted a method — i.e., the exclusive use of mathematical models, or mathematisation — to content (Sindzingre, 2017b).

In addition, mainstream economics is often confused with the policies that are inspired by it, and which are usually coined as 'neoliberalism'. 'Neoliberalism' is also notoriously difficult to define, as it does not form a coherent set of theoretical assumptions and subsequent policies. 'Neoliberalism' are more a nexus of policies that adapts to circumstances than a coherent set of theoretical hypotheses (Harvey, 2005; Steger and Roy, 2010; Blyth, 2013; Sindzingre, 2015). Confusion is also increased by the fact that 'neoliberalism' refers to various kinds of political economies, from democracies to the authoritarian exercise of power (Andersson and Godechot, 2018).

2.2. The difficulty in establishing indisputable distinctions

The literature is similarly vast regarding the features that would distinguish heterodox 2 from mainstream economics, similarly because of the plurality of the definitional features of 8 both perspectives.

^ It cannot obviously be the aim of an article to be an exhaustive review of both strands of

2 economic literature and their distinctive features. Rather, a series of assumptions is selected, S which are usually said to constitute differences between the two frameworks: on the side of | mainstream economics, the representation of the individual as a self-interested economic ^ agent, modelling as an exclusive method, and isolation from the other social sciences. It is argued that recent developments of mainstream economics have made it so that in fact these | features no longer constitute distinctive traits between the two conceptual frameworks.

CD CO

< Methodological individualism, and the selfishness of economic agents?

<

o o

<

iНе можете найти то, что вам нужно? Попробуйте сервис подбора литературы.

CD

X $

LU

Mainstream economics' methodological individualism could thus constitute an assumption that delineates a difference: yet heterodox models may also rely on individuated units to which a modeller assigns individualised rules of behaviour, e.g. agent-based models.

X X

< Equally, the assumptions that the economic agent is moved by her selfishness and by the

X

O

maximisation of her utility is often considered as an unambiguous difference between the ^ 'heterodox' paradigm, the latter refuting the universality of such an assumption, and the former supporting it.

On the one hand, the Walrasian framework of general equilibrium and perfect competition depicts an agent who is indifferent to others, because behaviours are driven by prices, and strategic behaviour has been conceptualised later, notably by game theory and behavioural economics. On the other hand, the fact that human beings are driven by some & interest, however, is difficult to refute - e.g. at least some 'striving to persevere in being', to paraphrase Spinoza - and moreover utility can be 'maximised' by behaviours that go against the apparent interest of an economic agent (as in 'unconditional commitments' and sacrifices of life for values, (Atran, 2016)). Differences actually relate more to the vectors of such interest, i.e. social groups rather than individuals (Sindzingre, 2017a).

t Mathematical modelling?

o5 Likewise, modelling, quantification, or the use of econometrics could also constitute

~ criteria of mainstream literature, as mathematisation is recurrently underscored in heterodox studies for being one of the main characteristics — and flaws — of the mainstream, while other (e.g., qualitative, analytical) methods would be privileged by heterodox economics. Yet post-Keynesian models, stock-flow consistent models, or agent-based models all use modelling, which can be as sophisticated as mainstream ones, e.g., DSGE models or others. Economics

of complexity, for example the pluridisciplinary research conducted at the Santa Fe Institute, which explores the emergence of social structures via, e.g., networks or agent-based models usually viewed as 'heterodox', typically relies on mathematics.

Equally, thinkers such as Hyman Minsky have highlighted the fundamental instability of financial markets and the subsequent possibility that economies follow a path of disequilibrium: yet he used 'mainstream' concepts and theories such as those of 'principal-agent' or moral hazard, and the later development of approaches such as behavioural finance, which can be viewed as 'mainstream' have supported the theses of disequilibrium paths (Veneroso, 2018). Conversely, at the beginning of the 21st century some studies in mainstream macroeconomics have put forward theoretical stances that questioned the neoclassical framework. Among many examples are Olivier Blanchard's suggestions of considering IS/LM and Philips curves rather than aggregate demand and supply, in line with a focus on economic instabilities (Brancaccio and Saraceno, 2017).

Policies?

Similarly, at the level of policies, international financial institutions that are viewed as typical supports of the mainstream framework, such as the IMF, contribute to the blurring of distinctions between what would be understood as 'orthodox' and 'heterodox' economic policies, which is compounded by the inherent lack of coherence of the set of policies gathered under the term of 'neoliberalism'.

For example, the IMF may support state intervention in line with its mandate of surveillance of the fiscal deficits of its members (in contrast with the World Bank, which is a development bank and has a different mandate). Likewise, in 2016 an IMF study acknowledged the failure of policies supported by the neoliberal framework (Ostry et al., 2016). Likewise, it has even been argued that the IMF has taken a heterodox stance in the mid-2000s as it recommended progressive taxation and intervention of the state in the economy (Ban and Gallagher, 2015). This has contributed to the blurring of distinctions, and the difficulty in finding necessary, sufficient, indisputable criteria which would separate the two paradigms.

Evolution and history?

Considering evolution or history as pivotal concepts could also distinguish heterodox perspectives from mainstream ones (e.g., the pioneering critiques of neoclassical assumptions q of market equilibrium and profit maximisation by Nelson and Winter, 1982; Dosi and Nelson, 1994)3. Yet game theory situates itself in an evolutionary perspective with the concepts of ^ learning and strategic behaviour (Fudenberg and Levine, 1998), and has biological models c as a background (Axelrod and Hamilton, 1981) (the theory of social interactions also refers S to an evolutionary approach, Durlauf and Young, 2001). The fact that these theories may -5 be at the borders of the mainstream framework remains a matter of debate (Friedman, ^ 1999). Similarly a methodology such as running iterations in order to observe adaptive and learning behaviour is used by mainstream and heterodox models (e.g., agent-based models). ^

Likewise, neoinstitutional economics has been built from the seminal studies in the economic history of the United States by Douglass North and Robert Fogel, and the literature ^ they inspired (e.g., Greif, (2006), and his analyses of the pre-modern Genoese and Maghribi ^ traders) shows that evolutionary approaches may be used within neoclassical or functionalist frameworks (e.g. functions of minimising transaction costs, preserving reputation, among ¡2 others mechanisms).

Equally, many models of long-run growth take into account history while remaining in — a mainstream paradigm, e.g. via post-Malthusian assumptions allowing for theorising the o relevant determinants of growth, notably the interaction between technological change and demographic transition (Galor, 2005); similarly, a vast literature has enriched the Solow cc

3 As also indicated by the name of the EAEPE, European Association for Evolutionary Political Economy...

O

or endogenous growth models with a variety of variables, including historical ones, e.g. variations in productivity, demography, 'institutions', etc., with many linkages with studies in world economic history, notably those analysing divergence across regions (Pomeranz, 2000; Clark., 2007).

Openness to other social sciences?

Similarly, openness to other social sciences is often said to characterise the heterodox framework and could constitute a difference between the two paradigms. Yet, mainstream economics increasingly claims that its openness to social sciences (while claiming not to be one of them) has modified several mainstream assumptions (Hedoin, 2010). For some, mainstream economics is even no longer neoclassical and has become pluralistic, being open to psychology and having abandoned the concepts of rationality, selfishness and equilibrium: experimental economics, behavioural economics and neuroeconomics would be the mainstream's 'new pluralist' subfields (Hands, 2015). Topics 'at the border' such as inequality or political economy, the latter using concepts from political science such as interest groups, elites, etc (Acemoglu and Robinson, 2012) are now fully integrated in mainstream economic studies. Simultaneously, it has been argued from within heterodox

00

th circles that heterodox economists could 'survive' only if they become more like mainstream cm economists (Lee, 2012).

^ Behavioural economics is an example of a branch of economics where several studies

claim to depart from the neoclassical framework (even being a 'revolution' in mainstream S economics, (Schettkat, 2018)). In line with H. Simon's findings on the bounded character of § rationality, behavioural economics argues that the results of many psychological, economic ^ and sociological laboratory and field experiments deviate from the framework of rational ^ choices, that neoclassical assumptions regarding utility or profit maximisation fail to explain human behaviour, and that human reasoning functions via heuristics and is characterised m by biases (among a vast literature, (Kahneman et al., 1982; Gigerenzer and Selten, 2001; Camerer and Loewenstein, 2004)). Similarly, behavioural economics claims that it takes into account not only the individual, the economic agent, but also the 'other' individuals -e.g. with concepts such as other-regarding behaviour, fairness, etc. Indeed, concepts such as 'altruism' and 'strong reciprocity', which derive from the behavioural perspective, have been analysed by economists often viewed as 'heterodox' (Bowles and Gintis, 2011) and have worked in a pluridisciplinary approach, e.g. with psychologists and anthropologists (Henrich et al., 2004). Behavioural economics has also contributed to blur the conventional distinctions between macro and microeconomics, as it has been used to reassess the theories of Keynes (Pech and Milan, 2009) as well as mainstream models such has DSGE models (De Grauwe and Ji, 2018).

X

<

CD X

3. Deepening three distinctions between the two frameworks

w It is argued that other distinctions may therefore delineate differences between the

a 'mainstream' and 'heterodox' conceptual frameworks and hence some theoretical cores of heterodox economics.

<

o 3.1. An 'heterodox' core: against reductionism, conserving

¡5 the complexity of the causalities?

Firstly, effective distinctions may relate to the concept of causality, as analytic reflections on causalities and mechanisms appear to be a core for heterodox economics (in particular, on the 'direct interdependence among many and heterogeneous agents' (Elsner, 2017)). In a complementary line, the reflection on the concept of 'truth' may also be a core for heterodox economics — understood as a reflection on the nature of the reality and how to represent it, the causal processes that occur in its elements, and the ways of approaching it.

0)

Reduction

Reflection on economic causalities and the theories that can represent them may be a core of heterodox economics, which constitutes a sharp distinction with the 'a-theoretical' stance that characterised a part of the 'applied turn' that has affected economics since the end of the 20th century. For example, a rising trend in economics, particularly since the beginning of the 21st century, such as the use of experiments (laboratory, field or 'natural' experiments) in order to underscore some relationships between two phenomena, constitutes a continuation of mainstream assumptions that causalities based on a 'as if' and on reduction produce valid representations of the world and its dynamics. Randomised controlled trials (RCTs) constitute an extreme case where theoretical a-prioris and assumptions on causalities are explicitly rejected (Sindzingre, 2018b). Even a recognised economist such as Angus Deaton (2015 Nobel Prize) has explained the epistemic impossibility of such a claim of 'a-theory' that would be a proof of scientificity: via the example of a typical mainstream method - where method has become the content — such as randomised experiments, he has shown that even in RCTs, theory is always required to explain the hypotheses and results (Deaton, 2010). Similarly, even mainstream studies have criticised the claim that the exploitation of 'big data' makes a-priori theoretical hypotheses useless. They warn against 'big data hubris', i.e. the claim that big data are a substitute for traditional data collection and analysis: 'big data' may not be 'big insights' (Buono et al, 2018).

A conventional argument in mainstream economics justifying modelling is that the reduction of the complexity of reality to elementary variables of a mathematical model can be a epistemologically a valid representation of that reality, as famously justified by Friedman (1953). The justification of models by the fact that they constitute a 'as if is also defended by philosophers of economics (Hausman, 2015).

Heterodox economists may also use sorts of 'as if, conceiving modelling as building surrogate devices that may have a heuristic value (Maki, 2009). Yet heterodox economists are particularly aware that a key problem is to be sure of the elements of reality and detection of causalities that are contingent and can be omitted in the modelling. They are more exposed to remember that the 'as if is not the thing, because reflections on epistemology — conditions of knowledge — and on methodology are important features of heterodox economics, and possibly among its cores.

From a philosophical perspective, 'scientific reductionism' may be a self-defeating form oo

■H

of scientism. It relies on a positivist view of scientific method, which is defined as the most o

rational way of thinking, the only method of verification recognised by positivism being

mathematics, logic and the empirical sciences (Cummings, 1998). As shown by Putnam

(1981), the criterion of 'scientific reductionism', for which only those statements that can

be verified via scientific norms are rationally acceptable cannot itself be verified on the

basis of such norms and is therefore not rationally acceptable. Putnam here highlights a

standard problem in philosophy, i.e. no argument in support of a criterial conception of

rationality can ever proceed on the basis of those criteria themselves — a wider notion of o)

rationality is presupposed, and as underscored by Cummings, reductionism is at the root of q

this impossibility in providing a criterion of significance because the positivist methods of ¡2

verification can never meet their ceteris paribus clause: in eliminating contingent conditions _j

of an observation in order to keep only logical analysis, reductionism in fact can no longer be g

refuted by experience. F

In addition, reduction is an operation that transforms concepts, which are nexuses of t

names, senses, references (as theorised by Gottlob Frege, (1892/1960)), denotations and w

connotations, and are situated in contexts - time and space: the removal of one of these

elements modifies the concept — e.g., going from a mental state to an 'utility' to a variable °

and finally to a number. A concept is an abstract construct and 'is' not a thing perceived in ^

the observable world: as is well-known, the concept of circle is not round, and that of dog does 3

o

o c

O

■H

£

X

<

CD

X $

0) LU

0) <

o

not bark. A concept (e.g. the concept of being X) is not a class (e.g., of five X), and abstract context-dependent concepts may not form a class of representative exemplars (Hacking, 2014). Concepts therefore imply complex causalities, which may involve different sciences (including different social sciences), and reduction may not conserve these causalities. Reduction of a concept may be, e.g., in a metaphoric mode (representing something by something else) or a metonymic mode (representing a whole by a part, e.g., the 'representative agent): in such a transformation, the meaning of what is represented may be fundamentally changed, as there is a fundamental uncertainty regarding what may be 'necessary' elements of a concept and what may be 'peripheral' or contingent elements. Establishing causalities between concepts is likewise threatened by reduction.

Moreover, it may even be argued that reduction is impossible, as any representation of reality is fundamentally context-dependent. In line with Wittgenstein (1953) or Kripke (1972, 1982), most concepts may be viewed as quasi-'proper names', with their reference being linked to specific time and space - and therefore not having the required property of stability and disambiguation for being modelled beyond specific and limited time intervals and geographical locations (e.g., 'money', 'right', 'democracy', etc, (Sindzingre, 2017b)).

Modelling

00 ■H

cm Modelling is not reduction, and modelling does not constitute a relevant distinction

^ between the mainstream and heterodox paradigms. The issue is not the fact of modelling. As

01

2 argued by Keen (2015), neoclassical mathematisation may not even be genuine mathematics, S and there may be non-neoclassical economics that are mathematical. The issue of the poor

| quality of the mathematics used by mainstream economists has even been underscored by ^ other mainstream economists, e.g. Romer (2015), who argued against the bad maths, or „ 'mathiness', of many mainstream studies. It is the modalities of the process of modelling that draw a distinction, and notably, it is the assumptions that may make the difference: m for example, Post-Keynesian modelling rely on hypotheses that differ from mainstream < macroeconomic models (Lavoie, 2015), e.g., they may assume the fundamental uncertainty o of the world (Lavoie, 2014).

Complexity economics uses modelling, but the latter is utilised in a way opposed to reductionism, i.e. according to 'bottom-up' dynamics. For example, agent-based models are

X -Û x

< microstructures that model the behaviour of agents in a context, assign rules to units and

X

O

observe the patterns that emerge with time (iterations) (Elsner et al., 2015) — even if one § limitation is that these may only reflect the rules ex ante assigned to these units (Sindzingre, 2018a).

Rather, a core of a 'heterodox' reflection is that mathematisation has an epistemic status distinct from 'truth', and the epistemological reflection that a method cannot substitute for a conceptual content.

3.2. Time, irreversibility, uniqueness

Secondly, the conceptualisation of time may draw a line of difference between the two paradigms. Time is linked to space, as both contribute to the context of an event. Time is also a dimension of the above-discussed issue of causality and the possibility to model causalities, for example regarding the possibility to build 'stylised facts' that could be reproducible.

H Conceptualising time

o5 As are the issues of reduction or 'true' causalities, time is not a problematic issue

~ for the 'model-platonism' that characterises mainstream economics (Kapeller, 2013), and mainstream models hypothesise the existence of equilibrium, homeostasis and time reversibility. This conception is unjustified, however, and closer to a 19th century view of mechanics than contemporary physics, though the latter is the science that mainstream economics has striven to imitate since this 19th century (Mirowski, 1984; 1989). Since the

iНе можете найти то, что вам нужно? Попробуйте сервис подбора литературы.

early 20th century most physicists would defend a plurality of times depending on the level of reality considered. For some pioneering physicists, time and the perception of its flow do not correspond to physical reality. In particular, the popular study of Rovelli (2018) has thus argued that reality may rather be a network of events on which human beings project the past, present and future: the universe is organised by the laws of quantum mechanics and thermodynamics (entropy), and time emerges from these laws.

Philosophy has long argued that time could be conceived as a succession of unique events (as famously written by Heraclitus, 'no man ever steps in the same river twice'), and could be characterised by irreversibility. Heterodox economics has always been aware of the difficulties regarding the conception of time (and causality) that would be appropriate for economic analysis, and has taken into consideration the possibility of path dependence, non-ergodicity and irreversibility.

Cumulative causation and lock-in

These characteristics of phenomena and notably under the dimension of time have been theorised, in particular, by David (1985) and Arthur (1994). Economic causation can thus be of a cumulative nature (going back to Allyn Young, 1928, or Nicholas Kaldor, 1981; Toner, 1999; Sindzingre, 2013) and depend on past states: path dependence may be defined as a phenomenon that possesses the dynamic property of non-ergodicity in stochastic processes (i.e. not having the 'ability eventually to shake free from the influence of their past states') (David, 2000). Other concepts also describe these dynamics that simultaneously refer to time and causality, notably those of initial conditions, lock-in (e.g., by technological choices) and self-reinforcing mechanisms, positive feedbacks, tipping points, threshold effects, trapping processes, 'attractors'. Systems can be locked by 'historical small events' (Arthur, 1989); 'small causes' may produce bifurcations and unexpected events, including 'big effects', and rather than steady states, divergence may occur. The above concepts contributed to the conceptual matrix of complexity economics (Arthur, 2013, 2014).

Such concepts have clarified hypotheses made by heterodox frameworks, though some of them, such as multiple equilibria, increasing returns or path dependence, have been analysed by mainstream studies, notably those of poverty traps (Azariadis and Stachurski, 2005; Matsuyama, 2009) or of structural change (Coniglio et al., 2018, from the capabilities framework developed by Ricardo Hausmann and Dani Rodrik, e.g. Hausmann et al., 2007). oo

For the post-Keynesian approach, for example, taking into account historical time is a more o

realistic assumption (closer to 'truth') than the assumptions of equilibrium, reversibility and ^

homeostasis that characterise mainstream models —and taking history into account does o.

not prevent the existence of time regularities, e.g. cycles (Lang and Setterfield, 2006-7, who .

endorse the Heraclitean view that 'we pass this way only once'). Likewise, path dependence ^

(e.g. cumulative causation, lock-in, hysteresis) has an impact on equilibrium or fundamental -g

uncertainty (Setterfield, 2015). q

Similarly, heterodox thought gives a crucial importance to the concept of context, as the o)

latter shapes, for example, the meanings and relevance of norms, in contrast with mainstream ¡5 conceptions of the individual or policies as units that are 'detachable' from contexts (an assumption of experimental economics). For heterodox economics, initial conditions matter, as well as the temporal dynamics that follow them. Moreover, the societies of which economic agents are members are part of these initial conditions.

< o

3.3. Links with other social sciences as an heterodox 'core'? The example w

of the links of the concept of norms with that of 'society' ~

Trying to conceive economics as a social science °

Thirdly, for mainstream economics 'openness' to other social sciences is, in fact, conceived ^

as a hierarchy, an absorption and eviction, according to an explicit 'imperialism' that is 3 justified in the name of a superior 'scientificity' of mainstream economics vis-à-vis other Ç

social sciences stemming from its use of mathematical modelling (Lazear, 1999; Fourcade et al., 2015). Yet in such annexation what is kept from the concept from the other social sciences is only what can be mathematised (Sindzingre, 2017b). Mathematising concepts from other social sciences, i.e. transforming them into variables that can be included in a mathematical model, change and may empty the meaning of the concept of that social science. Indeed, as any concept, the latter' meanings depend on its insertion within the nexus of other concepts built by that social science, and even more so as many concepts are made more complex due to their use by ordinary language (e.g. 'utility', 'interest', 'norm', 'individual', etc).

Behavioural economics is an example of a branch of mainstream economics that has been often presented as an example of the latter' 'openness' to other social sciences and even a departure from neoclassical assumptions. It may be argued, however, that behavioural economics rather represents the relaxing of some neoclassical assumptions, e.g. the inclusion of notions such as fairness or identity in the utility function. It may also be underscored that behavioural economics, in line with game theory (both sub-fields being closely related), still keeps the framework of methodological individualism: when behavioural economics claims that it takes into account other disciplines, the latter mainly consists in psychology (or neurology), which, even in its form of social psychology, keeps more a focus on the individual 3 than society; when it claims that it takes into account social features, it rather refer, in 8 fact, to the utility of individuals that depends on the behaviour and judgement of other ^ individuals: as in games, the framework of methodological individualism is conserved.

OI

In contrast, a commonality within 'heterodox' economics is that, despite the variety of approaches (from Marx to Veblen, Polanyi or Sraffa), it conceives economics as a social science, which tries to think social activities and social structures in their link with economic facts and behaviour (Lee and Jo, 2011). This constitutes a divergence from the evolution of mainstream economics after WWII and its use of concepts from social sciences: e.g., psychology (e.g., concepts of bias in rationality), political science (e.g., concepts of interest groups, elites), history (e.g., provision of long time series), sociology (e.g., concept

o

■H

x CD m

< of 'social capital), anthropology (e.g., concepts of 'institutions', social rules and norms). The

<

o o x

X

difficult task of building economic concepts that would take into account 'social' dimensions as conceptualised by the other social sciences constitutes a theoretical core of heterodox economics. This has been, for example, the research agenda of 'founding fathers' of < heterodox thinking such as Thorstein Veblen or Karl Polanyi. This was a commonality of o 'old institutionalism' (Thorstein Veblen, John R. Commons), which borrowed concepts from j social psychology of its time or from law and economics (Rutherford, 2001), and which put £ an emphasis on 'methodological collectivism' and 'socialisation' rather than methodological x individualism and 'individuation' (Samuels, 1990). Equally, the concepts of heterogeneity in agents and their behaviour, as well as that of collective learning, which are developed by, e.g., agent-based models in contrast with the neoclassical representative agent, are a dimension of this commonality - trying to provide accurate accounts of the complexity of a? societies.

LLl

<

CD

X $

¡2 An example: the concept of social norms

^ The concept of social norms allows for a deepening of these points. The concepts of social

z norms and institutions have been fully integrated in mainstream economics after the sop called 'institutional turn' of the 1990s stemming from the prize the Bank of Sweden gave ^ to Douglass North and Robert Fogel in 1993. Yet, though it has given rise to much debates o5 and has been used to argue that mainstream economics opened to other social science (e.g., ~ history, political science), what mainstream economics has kept from the concepts of norms and institutions are concepts that fit in the neoclassical framework (Harris et al., 1995). In particular, it may be argued that in its integration in mainstream economics the concept of norm (or 'rule', or 'institution') has been emptied from its dimensions involving society (or societies) — 'society' and not interactions of an individual with other individuals, an ontology

that is a core of behavioural economics, game theory, or principal-agent theories. Indeed, mainstream studies argue that they have long taken into account the role of social norms in individual behaviour. Yet these approaches remain within the framework of methodological individualism (e.g., in the studies of typical social norms such as those prevailing in non-market economies, kinship groups being analysed as capital market institutions, (La Ferrara, 2003) or in terms of strategic behaviour vis-à-vis kinship norms, (La Ferrara, 2007) or kinship systems evolving in order to enforce cooperation, Enke (2017). They leave unexplained why and how a social group can form from the juxtaposition of individuals, and why and through which mechanisms this meta-level (that of 'group') generates deontic beliefs that are able to impose norms of behaviour to members of this group, and moreover, their infinite variety.

Indeed, what mainstream economics has kept from the concept of social norms does not allow for an understanding of the concept of a society and the possible causalities the latter may have with the concept of individual, and in particular the pre-eminence of societies on the individual. Yet the latter is demonstrated by any careful analysis of social norms. This is already shown by evolution, where fitness in fact refers to that of kin groups (Hamilton, 1963; 1964). Equally, neurobiology has shown the existence in the human brain of neurons of 'empathy' for other humans ('mirror neurons', Preston and de Waal (2002), including in other social animals.

Norms typically involve cascades of cognitive processes, from names to mental representations and language (Sindzingre, 2018a). They also inherently involve social processes in that for norms to become more than private representations they have to disseminate — i.e. being considered as 'relevant' for oneself by more than one individual (Sperber, 1996).

For a norm to be relevant, a norm on that norm, i.e. a 'meta-norm', is necessary (a term that is used by game theory, e.g., Axelrod (1986), for example via the concept of peer pressure, Fudenberg and Levine (2016), yet within the methodological individualism framework of game theory). It is this 'meta-norm' that actualises an existing norm - political, religious, economic - and transforms it into a norm that an individual views as relevant for herself (as one of her many deontic mental representations). The key point is that these meta-norms are provided by a group: i.e. one of the many groups of which an individual, as soon she is born, is a member (whatever group it may be, including the group sharing the common

norm that group membership is detestable...). An example may be the 'pressure' of a group o

for an individual to follow a given norm: the norm or institution (written or unwritten) may ^

exists ex ante, but in all societies individuals may ignore it or choose not to comply with it:

it is the pressure of a group that make it so that one individual complies with a norm (via

whichever mechanism, mimicry, coercion, etc.). This pressure of a group may also be chosen

by an individual - even if the apparent cost for that individual is high in terms of welfare, as

shown by the innumerable examples in human history of sacrifices of life for the defence of a

(representation of) the identity of a group (Gomez et al., 2017). For a norm to be followed by o)

N individuals and to become therefore an observable economic fact, membership of a group ¡5

is a necessary prior: by definition one does not follow the institutions or norms of a group ¡2

one is not a member of, and conversely the common following of an identical norm generate _j

, , <

a group . g

This membership is prior to the autonomous agent that is hypothesised by mainstream f

economics, and this conceptual framework where social groups appear to be conceptually t

prior to individuals may be viewed as a 'core' of a heterodox approach. w

o c

O

■H

£

4. Conclusion

This article has explored the possible distinctions that may be highlighted between the 'mainstream' and 'heterodox' paradigms in economics, with the aim of isolating concepts and questions that could constitute theoretical 'cores' for the latter.

< cc

3

o

Firstly, it has shown the difficulties in defining and using the two expressions, and that many of the contrasts that are underscored in the literature are not unambiguous distinctions and that many conventional oppositions have in fact been blurred by the evolutions of both mainstream and heterodox economics, e.g. those related to methodological individualism, the selfish economic agent, modelling as a method or use of concepts of other social sciences.

In this context, in a second step, the article has demonstrated that three issues can distinguish the two paradigms and serve as foundations of theoretical 'cores' for heterodox economics: i.e. how to represent causality and model it; how to represent time; and how to represent the links between individuals and society - the latter have been analysed via the example of social norms, which confirm a representation of such links where social groups appear to be conceptually prior to individuals.

REFERENCES

Andersson, J. and Godechot, O. (2018). Destabilizing Orders: Understanding the Consequences of Neoliberalism: Proceedings from the MaxPo Fifth-Anniversary Conference, Paris, 12—13 January.

oo Aspromourgos, T. (1986). On the Origins of the Term 'Neoclassical', Cambridge Journal

o of Economics, 10, 3, 265-270.

™ Acemoglu, D. and Robinson, J. (2012). Why Nations Fail: The Origins of Power, Prosperity,

iy and Poverty, New York, Crown Business.

Q- Arthur, W. B., (1989). Competing Technologies, Increasing Returns and Lock-In by

^ Historical Events. Economic Journal, 99, 394, March, 116-131.

,2 Arthur, W. B. (1994). Increasing Returns and Path Dependence in the Economy, Ann

0 Arbor, University of Michigan Press.

>? Arthur, W. B. (2013). Complexity Economics: A Different Framework for Economic

| Thought, Santa Fe, Santa Fe Institute, SFI working paper 2013-04-012.

0 Arthur, W. B. (2014). Complexity and the Economy, Oxford, Oxford University Press.

^ Atran, S. (2016). The Devoted Actor: Unconditional Commitment and Intractable Conflict

g across Cultures. Current Anthropology, 57, 13, June, 192-203.

g Axelrod, R. (1986). An Evolutionary Approach to Norms. American Political Science

Review, 80, 4, December, 1095-1111.

Axelrod, R. and Hamilton, W. D. (1981). The Evolution of Cooperation. Science, 211, 4489, 1390-1396, 27 March.

Azariadis, C. and Stachurski, J. (2005). Poverty Traps, in Philippe Aghion and Steven k Durlauf eds., Handbook of Economic Growth, Amsterdam, Elsevier.

1 Backhouse, R. (2010). Review of Frederic Lee, A History of Heterodox Economics: to Challenging the Mainstream in the Twentieth Century. Economic History Review, 63, 1,

257-258.

Backhouse, R. and Cherrier, B. (2017). The Age of the Applied Economist: the □J Transformation of Economics since the 1970s. History of Political Economy, 49, 5, 1-33. § Ban, C. and Gallagher K. (2015). Recalibrating Policy Orthodoxy: The IMF Since the

o5 Great Recession. Governance, 28, 2, April, 131-146.

< Berta, N. (2000). Le marché dans les modèles de Gérard Debreu. Recherches Economiques

o de Louvain-Louvain Economic Review, 66, 3, 303-308.

3 Blyth, M. (2013). Austerity: The History of a Dangerous Idea, Oxford, Oxford University Press.

Bowles, S. and Gintis, H (2011). A Cooperative Species: Human Reciprocity and its Evolution, Princeton, Princeton University Press.

Boyer, R. (2017). Orthodoxie, hétérodoxies et capitalismes contemporains (How do Orthodoxy and Heterodoxies Analyze Contemporary Capitalisms). Revue de la Régulation, 22, Fall, special issue 'Financialisation and Social Classes'. (http://journals.openedition.org/ regulation/12626#ndlr)

X

-Û <

iНе можете найти то, что вам нужно? Попробуйте сервис подбора литературы.

CD X

O s

J ^

0)

Brancaccio, E. and Saraceno, F. (2017). Evolutions and Contradictions in Mainstream Macroeconomics: the Case of Olivier Blanchard. Review of Political Economy, 29, 3, 345-359.

Buono, D., Kapetanios, G., Marcellino, M., Mazzi, G., and Papailias, F. (2018). Big Data Econometrics: Now Casting and Early Estimates, Milan, Bocconi University, Baffi-Carefin centre working paper 82.

Camerer, C. F. and Loewenstein, G. (2004). Behavioral Economics: Past, Present, and Future., in Colin F. Camerer, George Loewenstein and Matthew Rabin eds., Advances in Behavioral Economics, Princeton University Press.

Clark, G. (2007). A Farewell to Alms: A Brief Economic History of the World, Princeton, Princeton University Press.

Coniglio, N., Vurchio, D., Cantore, N., and Clara, M. (2018). On the Evolution of Comparative Advantage: Path-Dependent versus Path-Defying Changes, Bari, Universita degli Studi di Bari, department of economics, working paper 1/2018.

Cummings, L. (1998). The Scientific Reductionism of Relevance Theory: The Lesson From Logical Positivism. Journal of Pragmatics, 29, 1-12.

David, P. A. (1985). Clio and the Economics of QWERTY. American Economic Review, 75, 2, 332-337.

David, P. A. (2000). Path Dependence, its Critics and the Quest for 'Historical Economics', Oxford, All Souls College, in P. Garrouste and S. Ioannides eds., Evolution and Path Dependence in Economic Ideas, Cheltenham, Edward Elgar.

Deaton, A. (2010). Instruments, Randomization, and Learning about Development. Journal of Economic Literature, 48, June, 424-455.

De Grauwe, P. and Ji, Y. (2018). Behavioural Economics is Useful Also in Macroeconomics: The Role of Animal Spirits. Comparative Economic Studies, 60, 2, 203-216.

De Vroey, M. and Pensieroso, L. (2016). The Rise of a Mainstream in Economics, Louvain, Université Catholique de Louvain, Institut de Recherches Economiques et Sociales (IRES), discussion paper 2016-26.

De Vroey, M. and Pensieroso, L. (2018). La question du pluralisme en économie : une mise en perspective, Louvain, Université Catholique de Louvain, Institut de Recherches Economiques et Sociales (IRES), Regards Economiques 137.

Di Maio, M. (2013). Are Mainstream and Heterodox Economists Different? An Empirical Analysis. American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 72, 5, November, 1315-1348. oo

D'Ippoliti, C. and Roncaglia, A. (2015). Heterodox Economics and the History of o Economic Thought, American Economic Association meeting. (https://www.aeaweb.org/ ^ conference/2015/retrieve.php?pdfid=376), published in Tae-Hee Jo and Zdravka Todorova. eds. (2016). Advancing the Frontiers of Heterodox Economics: Essays in Honor of Frederic S. Lee, London, Routledge.

Dobusch, L. and Kapeller, J. (2012). A Guide to Paradigmatic Self-Marginalization: Lessons for Post-Keynesian Economists. Review of Political Economy, 24, 3, 469—487.

Donaldson, D. and Storeygard, A. (2016). The View from Above: Applications of Satellite Data in Economics. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 30, 4, Fall, 171-198. ö

o c

O

■H

£

Dosi, G. and Nelson, R. R. (1994). An Introduction to Evolutionary Theories in Economics. i—

Journal of Evolutionary Economics, 4, 3, September, 153-172. _i

Dow, S. C. (2011). Heterodox Economics: History and Prospects. Cambridge Journal of g

Economics, 35, 1151-1165. f

Düppe, T. (2012). Arrow and Debreu De-Homogenized. Journal of the History of Economic t

Thought, 34, 4, December, 491-514. w

Durlauf, S. N. and Young, H. P. eds. (2001). Social Dynamics, Cambridge MA, MIT Press

and Washington D. C., Brookings Institution Press. °

Edwards, B. (2018). Sherlock of Trade: David Donaldson. Finance and Development, 55, ^ 2, June, 37-39.

o

Elsner, W. (2017). Social Economics and Evolutionary Institutionalism Today. Forum for Social Economics, 46, 1, 52-77.

Elsner, W, Heinrich, T. and Schwardt, H. (2015). The Microeconomics of Complex Economies: Evolutionary, Institutional, Neoclassical, and Complexity Perspectives, Amsterdam, Elsevier, Academic Press.

Enke, B. (2017). Kinship Systems, Cooperation and the Evolution of Culture, Cambridge MA, NBER working paper 23499.

Fourcade, M., Ollion, E., and Algan, Y. (2015). The Superiority of Economists. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 29, 1, 89-114.

Frege, G. (1960). (Über Sinn und Bedeutung, 1892), On Sense and Reference, in Peter Geach and Max Black eds., Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, 2nd ed., Oxford, Blackwell, 56-78.

Friedman, D. (1999). Evolutionary Economics Goes Mainstream: a Review of the Theory of Learning in Games, Santa Cruz, University of California, economics department.

Friedman, M. (1953). The Methodology of Positive Economics, in Essays in Positive Economics, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 3-43.

Fudenberg, D. and Levine, D. K. (1998). The Theory of Learning in Games, Cambridge 3 MA, MIT Press.

8 Fudenberg, D. and Levine, D. K. (2016). Whither Game Theory?, Cambridge MA, Harvard

^ University, department of economics.

Galor, O. (2005). From Stagnation to Growth: Unified Growth Theory, in Philippe Aghion and Steven Durlauf, Handbook of Economic Growth, 1A, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 171-293.

Gigerenzer, G. and Selten, R. eds. (2001). Bounded Rationality: the Adaptive Toolbox, Cambridge MA, MIT Press.

Gómez, A., López-Rodríguez, L., Sheikh, H., Ginges, J., Wilson, L., Waziri, H., Vázquez, A., Davis, R. and Atran, S. (2017). The Devoted Actor's Will to Fight and the Spiritual

o

■H

x

m Dimension of Human Conflict, Nature Human Behaviour, 1, 673—679. < Greif, A. (2006). Institutions and the Path to the Modern Economy, Cambridge, Cambridge

o University Press.

Hacking, I. (2014). Why Is There Philosophy of Mathematics at All?, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

-O X

< Hamilton, W. D. (1963). The Evolution of Altruistic Behavior. The American Naturalist,

X

O

97, 896, September-October, 354-356. j Hamilton, W. D. (1964). The Genetical Evolution of Social Behaviour, I and II. Journal

of Theoretical Biology, 7, 1, July, 1-52.

Hands, D. W.(2015). Orthodox and Heterodox Economics in Recent Economic Methodology. Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics, 8, 1, Spring, 61-81.

Harris, J., Hunter, J., and Lewis, C. M. (1995). Introduction: Development and Significance of NIE, in John Harris, Janet Hunter and Colin M. Lewis eds., The New co Institutional Economics and Third World Development, London, Routledge.

Harvey, D. (2005). A Brief History of Neoliberalism, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Hausman, D. M. (2015). Much Ado about Models. Journal of Economic Methodology, 22, 2, 241-246.

Hausmann, R., Hwang, J. and Rodrik, D. (2007). What you Export Matters. Journal of Economic Growth, 12, 1, March, 1-25. t Hedoin, C. (2010). Towards a Paradigm Shift in Economics?. A Response to James K.

w Galbraith, Books and Ideas, 17 June. (http://www.booksandideas.net/Towards-a-Paradigm-- Shift-in.html)

° Henrich, J., Boyd, R., Bowles, S., Camerer, C., Fehr, E. and Gintis, H. eds. (2004).

^ Foundations of Human Sociality: Economic Experiments and Ethnographic Evidence from

3 Fifteen Small-Scale Societies, Oxford, Oxford University Press. o

<

CÖ X

Hodgson, G. M. (2006). Characterizing Institutional and Heterodox Economics: a Reply to Tony Lawson. Evolutionary and Institutional Economics Review, 2, 2, March, 213-223.

Hong, H. (2018). Towards a Critique of Neoclassical Economics: how to Neutralize and Radicalize our Understanding of the Postulate of Independence of Agents and Goods, Seoul, Yonsei University, Economic Research Institute, working paper 119.

Kahneman, D, Slovic, P. and Tversky, A. (1982). Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

Kaldor, N. (1981). The Role of Increasing Returns, Technical Progress and Cumulative Causation in the Theory of International Trade. Economie Appliquée, 24, 4, 593-617.

Kapeller, J. (2013). 'Model-Platonism' in Economics: on a Classical Epistemological Critique. Journal of Institutional Economics, 9, 2, 199-221.

Keen, S. (2015), Is Neoclassical Economics Mathematical? Is There a Non-Neoclassical Mathematical Economics?, in Jamie Morgan ed., What is Neoclassical Economics: Debating the Origins, Meaning and Significance, London, Routledge.

Kripke, S. A. (1972). Naming and Necessity, in Donald Davidson and Gilbert Harman, eds., Semantics of Natural Language, Dordrecht, Reidel.

Kripke, S. A. (1982). Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language: an Elementary Exposition, Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press.

La Ferrara, E. (2003). Kin Groups and Reciprocity: A Model of Credit Transactions in Ghana. American Economic Review, 93, 5, December, 1730-1751.

La Ferrara, E. (2007). Descent Rules and Strategic Transfers. Evidence from Matrilineal Groups in Ghana, Journal of Development Economics, 83, 2, 280-301.

Lang, D. and Setterfield, M. (2006-07). History versus equilibrium? On the Possibility and Realist Basis of a General Critique of Traditional Equilibrium Analysis. Journal of Post Keynesian Economics, 29, 2, Winter, 191-209

Lavoie, M. (2014). Post-Keynesian Economics: New Foundations, Cheltenham, Edward Elgar.

Lavoie, M. (2015). Should Heterodox Economics Be Taught In Economics Departments, Or Is There Any Room For Backwater Economics?, Paris, INET Annual Conference, session 'Teaching Economics'.

Lawson, T. (2005). The Nature of Institutional Economics. Evolutionary and Institutional Economics Review, 2, 1, 7-20. oo

Lawson, T. (2013). What is this 'School' Called Neoclassical Economics? Cambridge o Journal of Economics, 37, 947-983. ^

Lazear, E. (1999). Economic Imperialism, Cambridge MA, NBER working paper 7300.

Lee, F. S. (2009). A History of Heterodox Economics: Challenging the Mainstream in the Twentieth Century, London, Routledge.

Lee, F. S. (2012). Heterodox Economics and its Critics. Review of Political Economy, 24, 2, 337-351.

o c

O ■H

Lee, F. S. and Jo, T.-H. (2011). Social Surplus Approach and Heterodox Economics. o)

Journal of Economic Issues, XLV, 4, December, 857-875. ô

Maki, U. (2009). MISSing the World: Models as Isolations and Credible Surrogate ¡2

Systems. Erkenntnis, 70, 1, 29-43. _j

Martins, N. O. (2013). Classical Surplus Theory and Heterodox Economics. American g

Journal of Economics and Sociology, 72, 5, November, 1205-1231. f

Matsuyama, K. (2009). Poverty Traps, New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, online. t

Mearman, A. and Archela, D. G. (2018). What do Heterodox Economists Say Heterodox w

Economics Is?, Leicester, De Montfort University, 20th Anniversary Conference of the

Association for Heterodox Economics (AHE), 5-7 July. °

Mirowski, P. (1984). Physics and the 'Marginalist Revolution'. Cambridge Journal of

iНе можете найти то, что вам нужно? Попробуйте сервис подбора литературы.

Economics, 8, 4, 361-379. ^

o

Mirowski, P. (1989). More Heat than Light: Economics as Social Physics, Physics as Nature's Economics, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

Nelson, R. R. and Winter, S. G. (1982). An Evolutionary Theory of Economic Change, Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press.

Ostry, J. D., Loungani, P. and Furceri, D. (2016). Neoliberalism: Oversold? Finance and Development, 53, 2, June, 38-41.

Pech, W. and Milan, M. (2009). Behavioral Economics and the Economics of Keynes. Journal of Socio-Economics, 38, 6, 891-902.

Phelps, J. M. and White, C. M. (2018). Social Psychology and Neoliberalism: a Critical Commentary on McDonald, Gough, Wearing, and Deville (2017), Journal of the Theory of Social Behaviour, forthcoming.

Pignol, C. (2017). La théorie de l'équilibre général, Lille, Presses Universitaires du Septentrion.

Pomeranz, K. (2000). The Great Divergence: China, Europe and the Making of the Modern Western Europe, Princeton, Princeton University Press.

Preston, S. D. and de Waal, F. B. M. (2002). Empathy: Its Ultimate and Proximate Bases. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 25, 1-72. ^ Putnam, H. (1981). Reason, Truth and History, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

° Ragni, L. (2018). Applying Mathematics to Economics According to Cournot and Walras.

^ European Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 25, 1, February, 73-105. z: Romer, P. M. (2015). Mathiness in the Theory of Economic Growth. American Economic

o Review, 105, 5, 89-93.

s Rovelli, C. (2018). The Order of Time, London, Allen Lane Penguin.

Rutherford, M. (2001), Institutional Economics: Then and Now. Journal of Economic ® Perspectives, 15, 3, Summer, 173-194.

Samuels, W. (1990). The Old versus the New Institutionalism. Review of Political g Economy, 2, 1, 83-86.

Schettkat, R. (2018). Revision or Revolution? A Note on Behavioral vs. Neoclassical Economics, Wuppertal, University of Wuppertal, Schumpeter School of Business and Economics, Schumpeter discussion paper 2018-5.

Setterfield, M. (2015). Path Dependency, New York, New School for Social Research, Department of Economics, working paper 1521.

Sindzingre, A. N. (2013). Growth Divergences and Cumulative Causation: Economics as a Social Science, Bordeaux, Congress of the Association Française d'Economie Politique (AFEP), 3-5 July.

Sindzingre, A. N. (2015). Whatever Inconsistencies and Effects? Explaining the Resilience of the Policy Reforms Applied to Developing Countries. Forum for Social Economics, 44,2, August, 159-178.

Sindzingre, A. N. (2017a). Understanding the Concept of Gift in Economics: Contributions ^ from Other Social Sciences. Eidos: A Journal for Philosophy of Culture (University of Warsaw, w Institute of Philosophy), 2, 4-20 (special issue 'Economy within Culture'). 3 Sindzingre, A. N. (2017b). Conceptual Impossibilities in Mathematisation? The Example

of 'Institutions', Budapest, Corvinus University, 29th Conference of the European Association for Evolutionary Political Economy (EAEPE), 19-21 October.

Sindzingre, A. N. (2018a). Concept and Causation: Issues in the Modelling of Institutions, Forum for Social Economics, special issue 'The Complexity of Institutions: Theory and Computational Methods', forthcoming.

Sindzingre, A. N. (2018b). Experiments in Economics and their Ethical Dimensions: o The Case of Developing Countries, Leicester, De Montfort University, 20th Anniversary < Conference of the Association for Heterodox Economics (AHE), 5-7 July. ëÉ Sperber, D. (1996). Explaining Culture: a Naturalistic Approach, Oxford, Cambridge

o MA, Blackwell.

X

<

CD

X $

Steger, M. B. and Roy, R. K. (2010). Neoliberalism: A Very Short Introduction, Oxford, Oxford University Press.

Toner, Ph. (1999). Main Currents in Cumulative Causation: the Dynamics of Growth and Development, London, Macmillan and New York, St. Martin's Press.

Veneroso, F. (2018). The Economics of Instability: An Abstract of an Excerpt, Annandaleon-Hudson, Bard College, Levy Economics Institute, working paper 903.

Weingast, B. R. (2018). The Many, Diverse "Main Points" of Adam Smith's the Wealth of Nations, Stanford, Stanford University.

Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical Investigations, Oxford, Basil Blackwell.

Young, A. A. (1928). Increasing Returns and Economic Progress. Economic Journal, 38, 152, December, 527-542.

oo

■H

o

CM

o c

o

■H

£

CD LU

CO <

o

CD

O <

cc

3

o

i Надоели баннеры? Вы всегда можете отключить рекламу.